1 / 50

International Congress of Linguists, Geneva, 21-27 July 2013

International Congress of Linguists, Geneva, 21-27 July 2013. Temporal Reference in Discourse: A Modality-Based Asymmetric Account? Kasia M. Jaszczolt University of Cambridge http://people.pwf.cam.ac.uk/kmj21. Outline. The modal supervenience of time

sheri
Download Presentation

International Congress of Linguists, Geneva, 21-27 July 2013

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. International Congress of Linguists, Geneva, 21-27 July 2013 Temporal Reference in Discourse: A Modality-Based Asymmetric Account? Kasia M. Jaszczolt University of Cambridge http://people.pwf.cam.ac.uk/kmj21

  2. Outline • The modal supervenience of time • The semantic representation of temporality: ACC operator on merger representations • Quantitative differences in ACC for representing qualitative distinctions P, N, F: • The Direct-Quantitative View • The Modal-Contextualist View

  3. What is expressed overtly in onelanguage may be left to pragmatic inference or default interpretation in another.

  4. ‘Tenseless’ languages St’àt’imcets(Lillooet Salish), British Columbia: Táyt-kan kelh Hungry-1sg.subj WOLL ‘I will be hungry.’ (Matthewson 2006) Paraguayan Guaraní: A-jahú- ta 1sg-bathe- PROSP (prospective aspect/modal) ‘I am going to bathe.’ (Tonhauser 2011)

  5. Thai: Pragmatic inference and defaults for temporality f3on t1ok rain fall (Srioutai 2006)

  6. From time to epistemic detachment ‘Why do we believe that events are to be distinguished as past, present, and future? I conceive that the belief arises from distinctions in our own experience. At any moment I have certain perceptions, I have also the memory of certain other perceptions, and the anticipation of others again.’ McTaggart (1908: 127)

  7. Time as Modality supervenience of the concept of time on the concept of epistemic detachment (temporal properties on modal properties in semantics)

  8. Supervenience A set of properties T supervenes on a set of properties M iff no two things can differ with respect to T properties without also differing with respect to M properties. ‘There cannot be a T-difference without an M-difference.’ adapted from McLaughlin & Bennett 2005

  9. Merger Representations for the Past Lidia went to a concert yesterday. (regular past) This is what happened yesterday. Lidia goes to a concert, meets her school friend and tells her… (past of narration) Lidia would have gone to a concert (then). (epistemic necessity past) Lidia must have gone to a concert (yesterday). (epistemic necessity past) Lidia may have gone to a concert (yesterday). (epistemic possibility past) Lidia might have gone to a concert (yesterday). (epistemic possibility past)

  10. Fig. 1: Degree of epistemic commitment for selected expressions with past-time reference

  11. Acc ├ p‘it is acceptable that it is the case that p’ (Grice 2001)

  12. ACCΔ ├ Σ ‘it is acceptable to the degree Δ that Σ is true’

  13. Fig. 2: Σ for ‘Lidia went to a concert yesterday.’ (regular past) Σ

  14. ‘Temporality and Epistemic Commitment: An Unresolved Question’in: K. M. Jaszczolt & L. de Saussure, eds (2013). Time: Language, Cognition and Reality. Oxford Studies of Time in Language and Thought vol. 1, Oxford University Press.

  15. Unresolved Question qualitative differences between P, N, F quantitative modal differences( in ACC)

  16. UQ: If The concept of time is underlyingly modal and supervenes on the degrees of epistemic commitment to (or detachment from) the narrated eventuality associated with the speech act by the speaker, then What is the exact correlation between the value of  that represents this degree of commitment in DS and the type of temporal reference: P, N or F?

  17. quantitative concept (ACC ) qualitative concepts (P, N, F) (i) correlation or (ii) P, N, F as quantitative differences

  18. Two possible solutions: • Direct-Quantitative View(DQ) • Modal-Contextualist View(MC)

  19. A and B theory McTaggart (1908) A theory: reality is tensed; time flows; (P), N, (F) are real. = psychological time B theory: reality is tenseless; there is no P, N, F out there and time does not flow. Events are real, and so is their ordering, but they don’t have pastness, futurity, or present actuality. = metaphysical time

  20. ? How exactly, if at all, does the value associated with the degree of epistemic commitment/epistemic detachment identify the ‘direction’ of detachment, into the past and into the future?

  21. Quantifying time This relative status of F and P is well conveyed in natural languages (hierarchies of epistemic modals and hierarchies of evidentials, Faller 2002).

  22. Quantifying time This relative status of F and P is well conveyed in natural languages (hierarchies of epistemic modals and hierarchies of evidentials, Faller 2002). The speaker’s choice of a construction with a stronger or weaker degree of trust in the truth of the embedded proposition, or an indicator of the kind of evidence (in itself weak or strong) can be taken as an indicator of the degree of commitment.

  23. ?Time as explanans: ‘may’ and ‘might’ λPλwλtw [wMB(w,t) & AT([t, _), wP)] There is a world wthat belongs to the set of worlds of the speaker’s epistemic state such that the given property is instantiated in this world at a certain interval. (Condoravdi 2002: 71, after Kratzer 1981/2012)

  24. ?Time as explanans: ‘may’ and ‘might’ λPλwλtw [wMB(w,t) & AT([t, _), wP)] There is a world wthat belongs to the set of worlds of the speaker’s epistemic state such that the given property is instantiated in this world at a certain interval. (Condoravdi 2002: 71, after Kratzer 1981/2012)

  25. Graded modality explained as an ordering of the worlds (Kratzer 1981/2012).

  26. The modal base (MB): a function from world-time pairs to sets of possible worlds that represents the epistemic state of the speaker. MB(w,t) = the set of worlds compatible with what the speaker knows at time t; P = property; [t,_) = an interval from t to infinity.

  27. Time as explanandum ACC as a base: ACCΔ=1 ├ Σ

  28. ?temporality is composed of diversified modal atomic concepts e.g. mayn>mayn+1>mayn+2... ‘>’ = the ordering of the strength of expressed commitment

  29. ?temporality is composed of diversified modal atomic concepts e.g. mayn>mayn+1>mayn+2... ‘>’ = the ordering of the strength of expressed commitment • (i) different degreesof detachment (values for n, n+1, n+2) or  (ii) different typesof detachment

  30. = the direct-quantitative view (DQ), the direct reliance on values of n, n+1, n+2... (ii) = the modal-contextualist view (MC), shifting the (arguably) qualitative differences between P, N and F to (arguably) qualitative differences between modal expressions on their occasions of use

  31. DQ and tenseless time (B-theory) B-theory(Oaklander 2002: 74; cf. Oaklander & White 2007; Le Poidevin 2007, 2011) • If all there is is duration and precedence (B-theory), then DQ is preferred: events occupy certain metaphysical and conceptual space in a way that allows the thinking agent to form an attitude to them – an attitude that includes the degree of certainty.

  32. DQ and tenseless time (B-theory) graded attachment translates into graded belief that a certain state of affairs is (tenselessly) real produces the illusion (‘time in the mind’) of ‘was/is/will be real’ (cf. Tallant 2013)

  33. DQ and tenseless time (B-theory) • At some level of atomic concepts, time passing is not only not real but P, N and F are not even in the mind at all.

  34. DQ and tenseless time (B-theory) • At some level of atomic concepts, time passing is not only not real but P, N and F are not even in the mind at all. • Instead there are degrees to which states of affairs are accepted by the agent.

  35. MC? MC is only possible (modal supervenience is preserved) if we can peg the qualitative differences in detachment pertaining to P, N, and F on linguistic semantic and conceptual distinctions.

  36. MC? • ‘There is no temporal difference without a modal difference’, but modal differences themselves are more than the lexicon and syntax reveal. radical contextualist approach to meaning: Default Semantics (Jaszczolt 2005, 2009, 2010), Interactive Semantics (Jaszczolt, in progress)

  37. MC = a result of pragmatic processing (inference + defaults) • post-Gricean principles of rational conversational behaviour • reliance on CPI (conscious pragmatic inference), or SCWD (social, cultural or world-knowledge defaults) of Default Semantics Supported by cross-linguistic empirical evidence (grammaticalisation of English will, default sense of Thai d1ay1II, pragmatic inference for ‘may’)

  38. MC and A-theory: An ‘asymmetry’ version • P and N are real and F unreal: ‘now’ is the edge of real time, and F simply keeps growing. • arguments from causation (Tooley 1997, 1999) • arguments from relational concepts (‘x (past) is real as of y (present)’, Button 2006, 2007)

  39. Reduction of MC + A-theory to DQ + B-theory • Accepting causation presupposes accepting a tensed world (Tooley’s asymmetric A-theory). But: • Tensed concepts can be broken down to and analysed in terms of tenseless ones. • Supervenience is ensured by relational properties: what facts are actual depends on the time at which they are assessed.

  40. Reduction of MC + A-theory to DQ + B-theory If the concept is underlyingly modal (remembering), then the DQ solution applies and we can have different values for different eventualities.

  41. value of  in ACC├ Σ >> Tom remembers PRO saying that time doesn’t flow. Tom remembers his saying that time doesn’t flow. Tom remembers that he had said that time didn’t flow.

  42. P/F asymmetry and the laws of physics Events are ordered in a unidirectional sequence. The second law of thermodynamics: disorder of a closed system (its entropy) increases with time (physical processes are irreversible). Real time does not flow: the past and the future have no objective sense.

  43. Psychological time (the human concept of time) Just as entropy is unidirectional, so is memory: memory of an agent increases and produces the illusion of the flow of time.

  44. Psychological time (the human concept of time) Just as entropy is unidirectional, so is memory: memory of an agent increases and produces the illusion of the flow of time. conceptual, epistemic reduction naturalistic reductionism

  45. “The labels ‘past’ and ‘future’ may legitimately be applied to temporal directions, just as ‘up’ and ‘down’ may be applied to spatial directions, but talk of the past and the future is as meaningless as referring to the up and the down.” Davies (2012: 11)

  46. Conclusions • Cross-linguistic differences in expressing time can be explained by a universal semantics in terms of the underlying concept of epistemic modality ACCΔ ├ Σ . • Temporality is not a primitive concept. It supervenes on the concept of epistemic detachment (ACCΔ ├ Σ’)from the truth of the merged proposition (Σ’). • The differences between P, N, and F are either (i) underlyingly quantitative rather than qualitative (DQ view) or (ii) the differences are qualitative and the value of  is contextually established (MC view). • MC is reducible to DQ.

  47. Select References • Button, T. 2006. ‘There’s no time like the present’. Analysis 66: 130-35. • Button, T 2007. ‘Every Now and Then, no-futurism faces no sceptical problems’. Analysis 67: 325-32. • Condoravdi, C. 2002. ‘Temporal interpretation of modals: Modals for the present and for the past’. In: D. Beaver et al. (eds). The Construction of Meaning. Stanford: CSLI Publications. 59-88. • Davies, P. 2012. ‘That mysterious flow’. Scientific American Special 21.1: 8-13. • Evans, N. and S.C. Levinson. 2009. ‘The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32. 429-492. • Faller, M. 2002. ‘Remarks on evidential hierarchies’. In: D. Beaver et al. (eds). The Construction of Meaning. Stanford: CSLI Publications. 89-111. • Grice, P. 2001. Aspects of Reason. Ed. by R. Warner. Oxford: Clarendon Press. • Higginbotham, J. 2003. ‘Remembering, imagining, and the first person’. In: A. Barber (ed.). Epistemology of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Heidegger, M. 1953. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer. Transl. by J. Stambaugh as Being and Time. 1996. Albany: State University of New York Press. • Husserl, E. 1928. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung IX. Halle: Max Niemeyer. Transl. by J. B. Brough as Lectures on the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time in: On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893-1917). Part A. 1991. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  48. Jaszczolt, K. M. 2005. Default Semantics: Foundations of a Compositional Theory of Acts of Communication. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Jaszczolt, K. M. 2006. ‘Defaults in semantics and pragmatics’. In: E. N. Zalta(ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.http://plato.stanford.edu/contents.html • Jaszczolt, K. M. 2009. Representing Time: An Essay on Temporality as Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Jaszczolt, K. M. 2010. ‘Default Semantics’. In: B. Heine and H. Narrog (eds). The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Analysis . Oxford: Oxford University Press. 215-246. • Jaszczolt, K. M. and J. Srioutai 2011. ‘Communicating about the past through modality in English and Thai’ . In: A. Patard & F. Brisard (eds). Cognitive Approaches to Tense, Aspect and Epistemic Modality. Amsterdam: J. Benjamins. 249-278. • Jaszczolt, K. M. 2012. ‘Cross-linguistic differences in expressing time and universal principles of utterance interpretation’. In: L. Filipović & K. M. Jaszczolt (eds). Space and Time in Languages and Cultures: Linguistic Diversity. Amsterdam: J. Benjamins. 95-121. • Jaszczolt, K. M. 2013. ‘Temporality and epistemic commitment: An unresolved question’. In: K. Jaszczolt & L. de Saussure (eds). Time: Language, Cognition, and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Kamp, H. and U. Reyle. 1993. From Discourse to Logic: Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic and Discourse Representation Theory. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  49. Kratzer, A. 1981/2012. ‘The notional category of modality’. In: H.-J. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (eds). Words, Worlds and Contexts – New Approaches to Word Semantics. Berlin: W. de Gruyter. 38-74. Revised edition in A. Kratzer. 2012. Modals and Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 27-69. • Le Poidevin, R. 2007. The Images of Time: An Essay on Temporal Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. • Le Poidevin, R. 2011. ‘The temporal prison’. Analysis 71: 456-65. • Łukasiewicz, J. 1961. ‘O determinizmie’. In: J. Słupecki (ed.). Jan Łukasiewicz. Z zagadnień logiki i filozofii. Pisma wybrane. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Transl. by Z. Jordan as ‘On determinism’ in: L. Borkowski (ed.). 1970. Jan Łukasiewicz: Selected Works. Amsterdam: North-Holland. 110-28. • McLaughlin, B. and K. Bennett. 2005. ‘Supervenience’. In: E. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/contents.html • McTaggart, J. E. 1908. ‘The unreality of time’. Mind 17. Reprinted in: J. E. McTaggart. 1934. Philosophical Studies. London: E. Arnold. 110-31. • Matthewson, L. 2006. ‘Temporal semantics in a superficially tenseless language’. Linguistics and Philosophy 29: 673-713. • Oaklander, L. N. 2002. ‘Presentism, ontology and temporal experience’. In: C. Callender (ed.). Time, Reality and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 73-90.

  50. Sattig, T. 2006. The Language and Reality of Time. Oxford: Clarendon Press. • Srioutai, J. 2004. ‘The Thai c1a: A marker of tense or modality?’ In: E. Daskalaki et. al. (eds). Second CamLing Proceedings. University of Cambridge. 273-80. • Srioutai, J. 2006. Time Conceptualization in Thai with Special Reference to d1ay1II, kh3oe:y, k1aml3ang, y3u:I and c1a. PhD thesis. University of Cambridge. • Smith, Q. 2002. ‘Time and degrees of existence: A theory of “Degree presentism”’. In: C. Callender (ed.). Time, Reality and Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 119-136. • Tallant, J.2013. ‘Time’. Analysis 73: 369-379. • Tonhauser, J. 2011. ‘Temporal reference in Paraguayan Guaraní, a tenseless language’. Linguistics and Philosophy 34: 257-303. • Tooley, M. 1997. Time, Tense, and Causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press. • Tooley, M. 1999. ‘The metaphysics of time’. In: J. Butterfield (ed.). The Arguments of Time. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 21-42. • von Fintel, K. & A. S. Gillies 2011. ‘“Might” made right’. In: A. Egan & B. Weatherson (eds). Epistemic Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 108-30. • von Fintel, K. and L. Matthewson. 2008. ‘Universals in semantics’. The Linguistic Review 25. 139-201.

More Related